
Michel Dupuis, "L'attention
et l'amour de l’Ordre dans la morale de Malebranche," L'attention au XVIIe siècle: conceptions et usages =Les études
philosophiques 2017, no. 1 (2017): 69-70
(59-71). On attentionner, see,
for example, the CNRTL.
![]() |
Department of Theology, University of Notre Dame |
From the Neothomist point of view, Neoplatonism seemed an ally of modernity, a movement that preceded it and sustained its idealisms. But the positive character of the current interest in Neoplatonism adheres to a reversal of that judgment. In the last third of the 20th century, it is Neoscholasticism rather than Neoplatonism that dreams of an objectivizing rationalism and an ontotheology. Towards 1960, the French discovered, despite the judgment of Étienne Gilson, that Heidegger would not object to [(ne ferait pas une exception à)] the identification by Thomas of God with ipsum esse subsistens. Thus, Neoplatonism, above all in its Proclean and Dionysian branches, and medieval thought in the measure in which it is Neoplatonic, becomes more interesting for every attempt to respond to the questions raised by modernity.Wayne J. Hankey, "Le role du néoplatonisme dans les tentatives postmodernes d’échapper à l’onto-théologie," La métaphysique: son histoire, sa critique, ses enjeux, Actes du XXVIIe Congrès de l’Association des Sociétés de Philosophie de Langue Française (A.S.P.L.F.), Québec, 18-22 août 1998) (Paris: Libraire Philosophique J. Vrin; Québec: Les Presses de l’Université Laval, 2000): 38-39 (36-43), citing Heidegger's 1959 "Le Retour au fondement de la métaphysique" and G. Prouvost, "La question des noms divins," Revue thomiste 98, no. 3 (1997): 485-511.