Wednesday, February 20, 2019
Argumentum ad "ea quae parent" (1 Sam 16:7)
Appeal to "those things that appear" (1 Sam 16:7 Douay-Rheims). I.e. appeal to "the outward appearance" (RSV) of a man, or argument from "outward appearance" (argumentum ab eis quae parent). As in (of Cardinal Raymond Burke on the dubia), "I'm sorry, but how can you take someone seriously who adorns himself like that?"
"The issues are . . . as substantial as the issues that came to the fore in the Nicene controversies in the fourth century".
"those who adopt a 'progressive' agenda in response to the
novelty of gay consciousness should be set free [via a 'Mexit'] to work out their own
confessional and theological commitments without the constraints that currently
muzzle their endeavors. What is at stake
here minimally is a theological and moral research program that should be
implemented by those who think that the future of the church rests with them. .
. . by my own lights I do not think that this research program will bear the
fruit its adherents promise; on the contrary I deem it to be a serious mistake
that represents a further schism in the history of the church. The issues are for me as substantial as the
issues that came to the fore in the Nicene controversies in the fourth
centur[y], in the division between East and West in the eleventh century, in
the debates about justification and grace in the sixteenth century, and in the
rejection of divine revelation in the nineteenth century."
William J. Abraham, "In defense of Mexit: disagreement and disunity in United Methodism," a paper presented at the GBHEM/AUMTS theological colloquy entitled "The Unity of the Church and Human Sexuality: Toward a Faithful United Methodist Witness," 10-12 March 2017, and published in Unity of the church and human sexuality: toward a faithful United Methodist witness (Board of Higher Education and Ministry, United Methodist Church, 2018), 21.
The quotations of Albert C. Outler (who invented "the Wesleyan quadrilateral" in order to make room for the theological pluralism represented by the United Methodist Church of 1968) that Abraham provides from the early 1970s (way back then!) are unforgettable. "we are being asked to vote for or against antinomianism, in an acid test," etc.
"If we cannot be relatively sure of what God has revealed to us then revelation is an empty concept."
William J. Abraham, "In defense of Mexit: disagreement and disunity in United Methodism," a paper presented at the GBHEM/AUMTS theological colloquy entitled "The Unity of the Church and Human Sexuality: Toward a Faithful United Methodist Witness," 10-12 March 2017, and published in Unity of the church and human sexuality: toward a faithful United Methodist witness (Board of Higher Education and Ministry, United Methodist Church, 2018), 14.
Cf. this.
The issue here is not the need for intellectual humility, or the need to be open to further evidence and light; the issue is whether revelation is essentially opaque and needs one more commission to set us straight on what God requires of us. If theology is yet one more theological seminar overseen by church officials and scholars—aided, of course, by the guidance of the Holy Spirit—then I, for one, dissent from this analogy with the life of the church. If we really want to resolve matters in the conciliar manner proposed by O’Donovan, then the train to take is the train to Rome. Vatican II supplies exactly the medicine that is needed to get us out of this dead end in moral theology. However, Rome alone is no more a solution than scripture alone [(15)].
"I would provide a more robust role for intuition in the epistemology of ethics" than Oliver O'Donovan
William J. Abraham, "In defense of Mexit: disagreement and disunity in United Methodism," a paper presented at the GBHEM/AUMTS theological colloquy entitled "The Unity of the Church and Human Sexuality: Toward a Faithful United Methodist Witness," 10-12 March 2017, and published also in the 2018 book of that same title.
Monday, February 18, 2019
The transhuman being as means, not end
"By th[is] characterization of excellence in terms of [(sur
le mode de)] power, the transhumanist being connects up with the superman of
Nietzsche. But this is nearly all the [two]
have in common. For the aspiration to
the transhuman is anything but [(tout sauf)] the cult of the genius whose spontaneous
[(primesautière)] superiority impresses his will on the ages of the human
epoque. The transhuman is in large part
a product of the human. The
technological [imperative of] improvement [(perfectionnement)] that determines its
contours does not come from nowhere. It
is the result of a human action. Now,
the instrumental[izing] thought that presides over its conception cuts into its
autonomy. One is [here] far from the
Kantian dignity of a quality that pertains to a being who can never be
considered as a pure means, but always also as an end in itself. The transhuman being is the means of the
realization of a certain concept of the human [(un certain concept humain)] in a
beyond-the-human subject [(au subject d’un au-delà de l’humain)], a fabricated
being (whatever the euphoria of progress and pathos of self-surpassment that
one puts into its fabrication). In this
sense, transhumanism poses the same basic problems as every selection [made]
prior to the conception—as much ideal as biological—of a human being."
Otto Schäfer, “Travail de construction ou de sape? Le chantier humain du transhumanisme,” Foi et vie 114, no. 4 (décembre 2014): 87-88 (80-94). I'm not entirely comfortable with his endorsement of Teilhard de Chardin, though (93-94).
Otto Schäfer, “Travail de construction ou de sape? Le chantier humain du transhumanisme,” Foi et vie 114, no. 4 (décembre 2014): 87-88 (80-94). I'm not entirely comfortable with his endorsement of Teilhard de Chardin, though (93-94).
Sunday, February 17, 2019
"We make no large claims"
"in the social world of corporations and governments private preferences are advanced under the cover of . . . the findings of experts. . . . . The effects of eighteenth-century prophecy have been to produce not scientifically managed social control, but a skilful dramatic imitation of such control. It is histrionic success which gives power and authority to our culture. The most effective bureaucrat is the best actor.
"To this many managers and many bureaucrats will reply: you are attacking a straw man of your own construction. We make no large claims, Weberian or otherwise. We are as keenly aware of the limitations of social scientific generalizations as you are. We perform a modest function with a modest and unpretentious competence. But we do have specialized knowledge, we are entitled in our own limited fields to be called experts.
"Nothing in my argument impugns these modest claims; but it is not claims of this kind which achieve power and authority either within or for bureaucratic corporations, whether public or private. For claims of this modest kind could never legitimate the possession or the uses of power either within or by bureaucratic corporations in anything like the way or on anything like the scale on which that power is wielded. So the modest and unpretentious claims embodied in this reply to my argument may themselves be highly misleading, as much to those who utter them as to anyone else. For they seem to function not as a rebuttal of my argument that a metaphysical belief in managerial expertise has been institutionalised in our corporations, but as an excuse for continuing to participate in the charades which are consequently enacted. The histrionic talents of the player with small walking-on parts are as necessary to the bureaucratic drama as the contributions of the great managerial character actors."
Alasdair MacIntyre, After virtue (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981), 102 ("The character of generalisations in social science and their lack of predictive power"). "the alleged laws . . . all turn out to be false and . . . so unquestionably false that no one but a professional social scientist dominated by the conventional philosophy of science would ever have been tempted to believe them" (84). "the generalisations and maxims of the best social science share certain characteristics of their predecessors — the proverbs of folk societies, the generalizations of jurists, the maxims of Machiavelli" (99). "the notion of social control embodied in the notion of [socio-scientific] expertise is . . . a masquerade. Our social order is in a very literal sense out of our, and indeed anyone's, control" (101).
"To this many managers and many bureaucrats will reply: you are attacking a straw man of your own construction. We make no large claims, Weberian or otherwise. We are as keenly aware of the limitations of social scientific generalizations as you are. We perform a modest function with a modest and unpretentious competence. But we do have specialized knowledge, we are entitled in our own limited fields to be called experts.
"Nothing in my argument impugns these modest claims; but it is not claims of this kind which achieve power and authority either within or for bureaucratic corporations, whether public or private. For claims of this modest kind could never legitimate the possession or the uses of power either within or by bureaucratic corporations in anything like the way or on anything like the scale on which that power is wielded. So the modest and unpretentious claims embodied in this reply to my argument may themselves be highly misleading, as much to those who utter them as to anyone else. For they seem to function not as a rebuttal of my argument that a metaphysical belief in managerial expertise has been institutionalised in our corporations, but as an excuse for continuing to participate in the charades which are consequently enacted. The histrionic talents of the player with small walking-on parts are as necessary to the bureaucratic drama as the contributions of the great managerial character actors."
Alasdair MacIntyre, After virtue (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981), 102 ("The character of generalisations in social science and their lack of predictive power"). "the alleged laws . . . all turn out to be false and . . . so unquestionably false that no one but a professional social scientist dominated by the conventional philosophy of science would ever have been tempted to believe them" (84). "the generalisations and maxims of the best social science share certain characteristics of their predecessors — the proverbs of folk societies, the generalizations of jurists, the maxims of Machiavelli" (99). "the notion of social control embodied in the notion of [socio-scientific] expertise is . . . a masquerade. Our social order is in a very literal sense out of our, and indeed anyone's, control" (101).
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)